DISCRETE MATHEMATICS
Chapter1
LOGIC AND SETS
1.1. Sentences
In this section, we look at sentences,
their truth or falsity, and ways of combining or connecting
sentences
to produce new sentences.
A sentence (or proposition) is an
expression which is either true or false. The sentence “2 + 2 = 4”
is
true, while the sentence “π is
rational” is false. It is, however, not the task of logic to decide
whether
any particular sentence is true or
false. In fact, there are many sentences whose truth or falsity
nobody
has yet managed to establish; for
example, the famous Goldbach conjecture that “every even number
greater than 2 is a sum of two
primes”.
There is a defect in our definition. It
is sometimes very difficult, under our definition, to determine
whether or not a given expression is a
sentence. Consider, for example, the expression “I am telling a
lie”; am I?
Since there are expressions which are
sentences under our definition, we proceed to discuss ways of
connecting sentences to form new
sentences.
Let p and q denote sentences.
Definition. (CONJUNCTION) We say that
the sentence p ∧ q (p and q) is true if the two sentences p,
q are both true, and is false
otherwise.
Example1.1.1. The sentence “2 + 2 = 4
and 2 + 3 = 5” is true.
Example1.1.2. The sentence “2 + 2 = 4
and π is rational” is false.
Chapter1: LogicandSets
page 1 of 9
DiscreteMathematics
Definition. (DISJUNCTION) We say that
the sentence p ∨ q (p or q) is true if at least one of two
sentences p, q is true, and is false
otherwise.
Example1.1.3. The sentence “2 + 2 = 2
or 1 + 3 = 5” is false.
Example1.1.4. The sentence “2 + 2 = 4
or π is rational” is true.
Remark. To prove that a sentence p ∨
q is true, we may assume that the sentence p is false and use this
to deduce that the sentence q is true
in this case. For if the sentence p is true, our argument is already
complete, never mind the truth or
falsity of the sentence q.
Definition. (NEGATION) We say that the
sentence p (not p) is true if the sentence p is false, and is
false if the sentence p is true.
Example1.1.5. The negation of the
sentence “2 + 2 = 4” is the sentence “2 + 2 = 4”.
Example1.1.6. The negation of the
sentence “π is rational” is the sentence “π is irrational”.
Definition. (CONDITIONAL) We say that
the sentence p → q (if p, then q) is true if the sentence p
is false or if the sentence q is true
or both, and is false otherwise.
Remark. It is convenient to realize
that the sentence p → q is false precisely when the sentence p is
true and the sentence q is false. To
understand this, note that if we draw a false conclusion from a true
assumption, then our argument must be
faulty. On the other hand, if our assumption is false or if our
conclusion is true, then our argument
may still be acceptable.
Example1.1.7. The sentence “if 2 + 2
= 2, then 1 + 3 = 5” is true, because the sentence “2 + 2 = 2”
is false.
Example1.1.8. The sentence “if 2 + 2
= 4, then π is rational” is false.
Example1.1.9. The sentence “if π is
rational, then 2 + 2 = 4” is true.
Definition. (DOUBLE CONDITIONAL) We say
that the sentence p ↔ q (p if and only if q) is true if
the two sentences p, q are both true or
both false, and is false otherwise.
Example1.1.10. The sentence “2 + 2 =
4 if and only if π is irrational” is true.
Example1.1.11. The sentence “2 + 2 =
4 if and only if π is rational” is also true.
If we use the letter T to denote “true”
and the letter F to denote “false”, then the above five
definitions
can be summarized in the following
“truth table”:
p q p∧q p∨q p p→q p↔q
T T T T F T T
T F F T F F F
F T F T T T F
F F F F T T T
Remark. Note that in logic, “or”
can mean “both”. If you ask a logician whether he likes tea or
coffee,
do not be surprised if he wants both!
Chapter1: LogicandSets
page 2 of 9
DiscreteMathematics
Example1.1.12. The sentence (p ∨ q) ∧
(p ∧ q) is true if exactly one of the two sentences p, q is true,
and is false otherwise; we have the
following “truth table”:
p q p∧q p∨q p∧q (p ∨ q) ∧ (p
∧ q)
T T T T F F
T F F T T T
F T F T T T
F F F F T F
1.2. Tautologies and Logical
Equivalence
Definition. A tautology is a sentence
which is true on logical ground only.
Example1.2.1. The sentences (p ∧ (q ∧
r)) ↔ ((p ∧ q) ∧ r) and (p ∧ q) ↔ (q ∧ p) are both
tautologies.
This enables us to generalize the
definition of conjunction to more than two sentences, and write, for
example, p ∧ q ∧ r without causing
any ambiguity.
Example1.2.2. The sentences (p ∨ (q ∨
r)) ↔ ((p ∨ q) ∨ r) and (p ∨ q) ↔ (q ∨ p) are both
tautologies.
This enables us to generalize the
definition of disjunction to more than two sentences, and write, for
example, p ∨ q ∨ r without causing
any ambiguity.
Example1.2.3. The sentence p ∨ p is a
tautology.
Example1.2.4. The sentence (p → q) ↔
(q → p) is a tautology.
Example1.2.5. The sentence (p → q) ↔
(p ∨ q) is a tautology.
Example1.2.6. The sentence (p ↔ q) ↔
((p ∨ q) ∧ (p ∧ q)) is a tautology; we have the following
“truth
table”:
p q p↔q (p ↔ q) (p ∨ q) ∧ (p ∧
q)
T T T F F
T F F T T
F T F T T
F F T F F
(p ↔ q) ↔ ((p ∨ q) ∧ (p ∧
q))
T
T
T
T
The following are tautologies which are
commonly used. Let p, q and r denote sentences.
DISTRIBUTIVE LAW.
Thefollowingsentencesaretautologies:
(a) (p ∧ (q ∨ r)) ↔ ((p ∧ q) ∨
(p ∧ r));
(b) (p ∨ (q ∧ r)) ↔ ((p ∨ q) ∧
(p ∨ r)).
DE MORGAN LAW.
Thefollowingsentencesaretautologies:
(a) (p ∧ q) ↔ (p ∨ q);
(b) (p ∨ q) ↔ (p ∧ q).
INFERENCE LAW.
Thefollowingsentencesaretautologies:
(a) (MODUS PONENS) (p ∧ (p → q)) →
q;
(b) (MODUS TOLLENS) ((p → q) ∧ q) →
p;
(c) (LAW OF SYLLOGISM) ((p → q) ∧
(q → r)) → (p → r).
Chapter1: LogicandSets
page 3 of 9
DiscreteMathematics
These tautologies can all be
demonstrated by truth tables. However, let us try to prove the first
Distributive law here.
Suppose first of all that the sentence
p ∧ (q ∨ r) is true. Then the two sentences p, q ∨ r are both
true. Since the sentence q ∨ r is
true, at least one of the two sentences q, r is true. Without loss
of
generality, assume that the sentence q
is true. Then the sentence p∧q is true. It follows that the
sentence
(p ∧ q) ∨ (p ∧ r) is true.
Suppose now that the sentence (p ∧ q)
∨ (p ∧ r) is true. Then at least one of the two sentences (p ∧
q),
(p ∧ r) is true. Without loss of
generality, assume that the sentence p ∧ q is true. Then the two
sentences
p, q are both true. It follows that the
sentence q ∨ r is true, and so the sentence p ∧ (q ∨ r) is
true.
It now follows that the two sentences p
∧ (q ∨ r) and (p ∧ q) ∨ (p ∧ r) are either both true or
both false,
as the truth of one implies the truth
of the other. It follows that the double conditional (p ∧ (q ∨
r)) ↔
((p ∧ q) ∨ (p ∧ r)) is a
tautology.
Definition. We say that two sentences p
and q are logically equivalent if the sentence p ↔ q is a
tautology.
Example1.2.7. The sentences p → q and
q → p are logically equivalent. The latter is known as the
contrapositive of the former.
Remark. The sentences p → q and q →
p are not logically equivalent. The latter is known as the
converse of the former.
1.3. Sentential Functions and Sets
In many instances, we have sentences,
such as “x is even”, which contains one or more variables. We
shall call them sentential functions
(or propositional functions).
Let us concentrate on our example “x
is even”. This sentence is true for certain values of x, and is
false for others. Various questions
arise:
• What values of x do we permit?
• Is the statement true for all such
values of x in question?
• Is the statement true for some such
values of x in question?
To answer the first of these questions,
we need the notion of a universe. We therefore need to consider
sets.
We shall treat the word “set” as a
word whose meaning everybody knows. Sometimes we use the
synonyms “class” or “collection”.
However, note that in some books, these words may have different
meanings!
The important thing about a set is what
it contains. In other words, what are its members? Does it
have any? If P is a set and x is an
element of P , we write x ∈ P .
A set is usually described in one of
the two following ways:
• By enumeration,e.g. {1, 2, 3}
denotes the set consisting of the numbers 1, 2, 3 and nothing else;
• By a defining property (sentential
function) p(x). Here it is important to define a universe U to
which all the x have to belong. We then
write P = {x : x ∈ U and p(x) is true} or, simply,
P = {x : p(x)}.
The set with no elements is called the
empty set and denoted by ∅.
Chapter1: LogicandSets
page 4 of 9
DiscreteMathematics
Example1.3.1. N = {1, 2, 3, 4, 5, ...}
is called the set of natural numbers.
Example1.3.2. Z = {. . . , −2, −1,
0, 1, 2, . . .} is called the set of integers.
Example1.3.3. {x : x ∈ N and − 2 <
x < 2} = {1}.
Example1.3.4. {x : x ∈ Z and − 2 <
x < 2} = {−1, 0, 1}.
Example1.3.5. {x : x ∈ N and − 1 <
x < 1} = ∅.
1.4. Set Functions
Suppose that the sentential functions
p(x), q(x) are related to sets P , Q with respect to a given
universe,
i.e. P = {x : p(x)} and Q = {x : q(x)}.
We define
• the intersection P ∩ Q = {x :
p(x) ∧ q(x)};
• the union P ∪ Q = {x : p(x) ∨
q(x)};
• the complement P = {x : p(x)}; and
• the difference P \ Q = {x : p(x) ∧
q(x)}.
The above are also sets. It is not
difficult to see that
• P ∩ Q = {x : x ∈ P and x ∈
Q};
• P ∪ Q = {x : x ∈ P or x ∈
Q};
• P = {x : x ∈ P }; and
• P \ Q = {x : x ∈ P and x ∈ Q}.
We say that the set P is a subset of
the set Q, denoted by P ⊆ Q or by Q ⊇ P , if every element of P
is an element of Q. In other words, if
we have P = {x : p(x)} and Q = {x : q(x)} with respect to some
universe U , then we have P ⊆ Q if
and only if the sentence p(x) → q(x) is true for all x ∈ U .
We say that two sets P and Q are equal,
denoted by P = Q, if they contain the same elements,i.e.
if each is a subset of the other,i.e.
if P ⊆ Q and Q ⊆ P .
Furthermore, we say that P is a proper
subset of Q, denoted by P ⊂ Q or by Q ⊃ P , if P ⊆ Q and
P = Q.
The following results on set functions
can be deduced from their analogues in logic.
DISTRIBUTIVE LAW. If P, Q, R
aresets,then
(a) P ∩ (Q ∪ R) = (P ∩ Q) ∪ (P
∩ R);
(b) P ∪ (Q ∩ R) = (P ∪ Q) ∩ (P
∪ R).
DE MORGAN LAW. If P, Q
aresets,thenwithrespecttoauniverse
(a) (P ∩ Q) = P ∪ Q;
(b) (P ∪ Q) = P ∩ Q.
U,
We now try to deduce the first
Distributive law for set functions from the first Distributive law
for
sentential functions.
Suppose that the sentential functions
p(x), q(x), r(x) are related to sets P , Q, R with respect to a
given universe,i.e. P = {x : p(x)}, Q =
{x : q(x)} and R = {x : r(x)}. Then
P ∩ (Q ∪ R) = {x : p(x) ∧ (q(x) ∨
r(x))}
and
(P ∩ Q) ∪ (P ∩ R) = {x : (p(x) ∧
q(x)) ∨ (p(x) ∧ r(x))}.
Chapter1: LogicandSets
page 5 of 9
DiscreteMathematics
Suppose that x ∈ P ∩ (Q ∪ R).
Then p(x) ∧ (q(x) ∨ r(x)) is true. By the first Distributive law
for
sentential functions, we have that
(p(x) ∧ (q(x) ∨ r(x))) ↔ ((p(x) ∧
q(x)) ∨ (p(x) ∧ r(x)))
is a tautology. It follows that (p(x) ∧
q(x)) ∨ (p(x) ∧ r(x)) is true, so that x ∈ (P ∩ Q) ∪ (P ∩
R). This
gives
P ∩ (Q ∪ R) ⊆ (P ∩ Q) ∪ (P ∩
R).
(1)
Suppose now that x ∈ (P ∩ Q) ∪ (P
∩ R). Then (p(x) ∧ q(x)) ∨ (p(x) ∧ r(x)) is true. It follows
from the
first Distributive law for sentential
functions that p(x) ∧ (q(x) ∨ r(x)) is true, so that x ∈ P ∩
(Q ∪ R).
This gives
(P ∩ Q) ∪ (P ∩ R) ⊆ P ∩ (Q ∪
R).
(2)
The result now follows on combining (1)
and (2).
1.5. Quantifier Logic
Let us return to the example “x is
even” at the beginning of Section 1.3.
Suppose now that we restrict x to lie
in the set Z of all integers. Then the sentence “x is even” is
only
true for some x in Z. It follows that
the sentence “some x ∈ Z are even” is true, while the sentence
“all
x ∈ Z are even” is false.
In general, consider a sentential
function of the form p(x), where the variable x lies in some clearly
stated set. We can then consider the
following two sentences:
• ∀x, p(x) (for all x, p(x) is
true); and
• ∃x, p(x) (for some x, p(x) is
true).
Definition. The symbols ∀ (for all)
and ∃ (for some) are called the universal quantifier and the exis-
tential quantifier respectively.
Note that the variable x is a “dummy
variable”. There is no difference between writing ∀x, p(x) or
writing ∀y, p(y).
Example1.5.1. (LAGRANGE’S THEOREM)
Every natural number is the sum of the squares of four
integers. This can be written, in
logical notation, as
∀n ∈ N, ∃a, b, c, d ∈ Z, n = a2
+ b2 + c2 + d2 .
Example1.5.2. (GOLDBACH CONJECTURE)
Every even natural number greater than 2 is the sum
of two primes. This can be written, in
logical notation, as
∀n ∈ N \ {1}, ∃p, q prime, 2n = p
+ q.
It is not yet known whether this is
true or not. This is one of the greatest unsolved problems in
mathematics.
1.6. Negation
Our main concern is to develop a rule
for negating sentences with quantifiers. Let me start by saying
that you are all fools. Naturally, you
will disagree, and some of you will complain. So it is natural to
suspect that the negation of the
sentence ∀x, p(x) is the sentence ∃x, p(x).
Chapter1: LogicandSets
page 6 of 9
DiscreteMathematics
There is another way to look at this.
Let U be the universe for all the x. Let P = {x : p(x)}. Suppose
first of all that the sentence ∀x,
p(x) is true. Then P = U , so P = ∅. But P = {x : p(x)}, so that
if
the sentence ∃x, p(x) were true, then
P = ∅, a contradiction. On the other hand, suppose now that the
sentence ∀x, p(x) is false. Then P =
U , so that P = ∅. It follows that the sentence ∃x, p(x) is
true.
Now let me moderate a bit and say that
some of you are fools. You will still complain, so perhaps
none of you are fools. It is then
natural to suspect that the negation of the sentence ∃x, p(x) is
the
sentence ∀x, p(x).
To summarize, we simply “change the
quantifier to the other type and negate the sentential function”.
Suppose now that we have something more
complicated. Let us apply bit by bit our simple rule. For
example, the negation of
∀x, ∃y, ∀z, ∀w, p(x, y, z, w)
is
∃x, (∃y, ∀z, ∀w, p(x, y, z,
w)),
which is
∃x, ∀y, (∀z, ∀w, p(x, y, z,
w)),
which is
∃x, ∀y, ∃z, (∀w, p(x, y, z,
w)),
which is
∃x, ∀y, ∃z, ∃w, p(x, y, z, w).
It is clear that the rule is the
following: Keep the variables in their original order. Then, alter
all the
quantifiers. Finally, negate the
sentential function.
Example1.6.1. The negation of the
Goldbach conjecture is, in logical notation,
∃n ∈ N \ {1}, ∀p, q prime, 2n = p
+ q.
In other words, there is an even
natural number greater than 2 which is not the sum of two primes. In
summary, to disprove the Goldbach
conjecture, we simply need one counterexample!
Chapter1: LogicandSets
page 7 of 9
DiscreteMathematics
ProblemsforChapter1
1. Using truth tables or otherwise,
check that each of the following is a tautology:
a) p → (p ∨ q)
b) ((p ∧ q) → q) → (p → q)
c) p → (q → p)
d) (p ∨ (p ∧ q)) ↔ p
e) (p → q) ↔ (q → p)
2. Decide (and justify) whether each of
the following is a tautology:
a) (p ∨ q) → (q → (p ∧ q))
b) (p → (q → r)) → ((p → q) →
(p → r))
c) ((p ∨ q) ∧ r) ↔ (p ∨ (q ∧
r))
d) (p ∧ q ∧ r) → (s ∨ t)
e) (p ∧ q) → (p → q)
f) p → q ↔ (p → q)
g) (p ∧ q ∧ r) ↔ (p → q ∨ (p
∧ r))
h) ((r ∨ s) → (p ∧ q)) → (p →
(q → (r ∨ s)))
i) p → (q ∧ (r ∨ s))
j) (p → q ∧ (r ↔ s)) → (t →
u)
k) (p ∧ q) ∨ r ↔ ((p ∨ q) ∧
r)
l) (p ← q) ← (q ← p).
m) (p ∧ (q ∨ (r ∧ s))) ↔ ((p ∧
q) ∨ (p ∧ r ∧ s))
3. For each of the following, decide
whether the statement is true or false, and justify your assertion:
a) If p is true and q is false, then p
∧ q is true.
b) If p is true, q is false and r is
false, then p ∨ (q ∧ r) is true.
c) The sentence (p ↔ q) ↔ (q ↔ p)
is a tautology.
d) The sentences p ∧ (q ∨ r) and (p
∨ q) ∧ (p ∨ r) are logically equivalent.
4. List the elements of each of the
following sets:
a) {x ∈ N : x2 < 45}
c) {x ∈ R : x2 + 2x = 0}
e) {x ∈ Z : x4 = 1}
b) {x ∈ Z : x2 < 45}
d) {x ∈ Q : x2 + 4 = 6}
f) {x ∈ N : x4 = 1}
5. How many elements are there in each
of the following sets? Are the sets all different?
a) ∅
b) {∅}
c) {{∅}}
d) {∅, {∅}}
e) {∅, ∅}
6. Let U = {a, b, c, d}, P = {a, b} and
Q = {a, c, d}. Write down the elements of the following sets:
a) P ∪ Q
b) P ∩ Q
c) P
d) Q
7. Let U = R, A = {x ∈ R : x > 0},
B = {x ∈ R : x > 1} and C = {x ∈ R : x < 2}. Find each of
the
following sets:
a) A ∪ B
b) A ∪ C
c) B ∪ C
d) A ∩ B
e) A ∩ C
f) B ∩ C
g) A
h) B
i) C
j) A \ B
k) B \ C
8. List all the subsets of the set {1,
2, 3}. How many subsets are there?
9. A, B, C, D are sets such that A ∪
B = C ∪ D, and both A ∩ B and C ∩ D are empty.
a) Show by examples that A ∩ C and B
∩ D can be empty.
b) Show that if C ⊆ A, then B ⊆ D.
10. Suppose that P , Q and R are
subsets of N. For each of the following, state whether or not the
statement is true, and justify your
assertion by studying the analogous sentences in logic:
a) P ∪ (Q ∩ R) = (P ∪ Q) ∩ (P ∪
R).
b) P ⊆ Q if and only if Q ⊆ P .
c) If P ⊆ Q and Q ⊆ R, then P ⊆
R.
Chapter1: LogicandSets
page 8 of 9
DiscreteMathematics
11. For each of the following
sentences, write down the sentence in logical notation, negate the
sentence,
and say whether the sentence or its
negation is true:
a) Given any integer, there is a larger
integer.
b) There is an integer greater than all
other integers.
c) Every even number is a sum of two
odd numbers.
d) Every odd number is a sum of two
even numbers.
e) The distance between any two complex
numbers is positive.
f) All natural numbers divisible by 2
and by 3 are divisible by 6.
[Notation: Write x | y if x divides
y.]
g) Every integer is a sum of the
squares of two integers.
h) There is no greatest natural
number.
12. For each of the following
sentences, express the sentence in words, negate the sentence, and
say
whether the sentence or its negation is
true:
a) ∀z ∈ N, z 2 ∈ N
b) ∀x ∈ Z, ∀y ∈ Z, ∃z ∈ Z,
z 2 = x2 + y 2
c) ∀x ∈ Z, ∀y ∈ Z, (x > y) →
(x = y)
d) ∀x, y, z ∈ R, ∃w ∈ R, x2 + y
2 + z 2 = 8w
13. Let p(x, y) be a sentential
function with variables x and y. Discuss whether each of the
following is
true on logical grounds only:
a) (∃x, ∀y, p(x, y)) → (∀y, ∃x,
p(x, y))
b) (∀y, ∃x, p(x, y)) → (∃x, ∀y,
p(x, y))
Chapter1: LogicandSets
page 9 of 9
No comments:
Post a Comment